JOHNMACKAY.NET

The Architecture of Possibility

How a Forgotten Framework Resolves Our Oldest Debate

...

architecture-of-possibility-01 Caption: Impossible Stairs. Rendered by nano banana in homage to perspective japonaise no. 354, color lithograph by Oscar Reutersvärd—the Father of the impossible image.

You’ve felt it before. That quiet tension when you hear that every choice might be an illusion, pre-written by the laws of physics. Or the vertigo of learning that at its heart, reality might be a game of chance. For centuries, we’ve been presented with a binary, almost tribal, choice: is the universe a deterministic clockwork or a probabilistic casino? We frame our philosophies, our sciences, and even our sense of self around this divide. But what if this entire debate is built on a shared, silent assumption—one so fundamental we’ve forgotten to question it?

This isn't just a philosophical puzzle; it's a question about the very architecture of your reality. What is truly possible for you tomorrow? What is necessary? The answers hinge on something called modal structure—the hidden scaffolding of possibility and necessity that makes both determinism and probability intelligible concepts in the first place. We’re about to embark on a journey to expose this framework and, in doing so, discover a third path that dissolves the ancient feud. This is the story of a universe that is neither a sterile clock nor a chaotic dice roll, but a living, breathing conference of difference.

The Classical Stalemate: One Path or Many?

Our story begins not in a lab, but with the ancient Greeks, wrestling with fate. The concept of Heimarmene (fate) suggested a fixed, unchangeable future, while Aristotle’s famous sea battle puzzle introduced a logical crack in this idea: if a statement about a future event is already true or false today, does that mean the outcome is necessary?[1] Or is it merely possible? This was the first conscious stumble into the realm of modal logic—the study of necessity and possibility.

The scientific revolution seemed to settle the score. Newton’s laws and Laplace’s demon cemented a rigid, unforgiving modal structure. In this view, the universe has exactly one possible future. The entire cosmic movie is already encoded in the first frame. Probability, here, was merely a measure of our human ignorance—a useful tool for gamblers and statisticians, but not a real feature of the world. The scaffolding allowed for no alternative paths.

This is the conceptual leap that changes everything. The 20th century dynamited this clockwork universe. Quantum mechanics didn’t just add uncertainty; it proposed a radically different modal structure. The future wasn't fixed; it was a probability distribution. Multiple potential outcomes were objectively real, each with its own 'chance' of occurring. Probability became ontic—a fundamental part of reality's fabric, not just in our minds. Philosophers like David Lewis gave us the language to describe this shift with 'possible worlds,' framing determinism as a universe with only one accessible future world and indeterminism as one with many.

The Modern Battlefield: Where the Debate Burns Hot

So where does this leave us today? Stuck in a series of flashpoints that all point back to the same core question: what is the true modal structure of our world?

Think of it not as a fight over events, but over the rules of the game itself. We’ve been so focused on the players (determinism vs. probability) that we’ve ignored the game board—the modal structure that gives them meaning.

The Conference of Difference: A Third Path Emerges

What if we’ve been asking the wrong question? The Conference of Difference (CoD) model, derived from the ontological principles of the Gospel of Being, proposes a radical reframing. It doesn’t choose a side in the old war. Instead, it reveals that determinism and probability are not opponents, but rather, walk hand-in-hand to transform existence.[5]

The model introduces a simple but profound two-tiered ontology. Imagine reality as an unstoppable river flowing downhill. The meta-process—the relentless pull of gravity that ensures the water will flow—is deterministic. This is the non-negotiable, invariant principle that all existence is a conference of difference [6]. It is the absolute law that being is a transformative verb, a constant 'bearing together' that creates relation and matter, not void or freedom [7]. This deterministic process is the engine of existence, observed from quantum fields to human conversations.

If this seems abstract, you're in good company. Now, look at the water itself. The specific moments—where eddies of water intersect forming different bubbles, splashes and temporary currents—they are not pre-determined. They exist in a state of graded possibility, a 'granting of leave' to various potentials [8]. The actual result that emerges is probabilistic, a function of the specific differences in conference with other differences, their relative power or ability, and the path of least resistance toward a new, temporary equilibrium [9].

Here’s the magic: the modal structure is the dynamic interface of these two levels. It is the living, evolving conference of difference that defines, at any given moment, the current landscape of potential relations and necessities.[10] It’s the constantly updating map of what is possible and necessary right now, born from the interaction between the deterministic engine and the probabilistic terrain.

Convergence, Divergence, and a New Synthesis

So, how does this model speak to the old doctrines? It doesn’t dismiss them; it situates them.

It converges with determinism by affirming the world’s profound regularities. The future is constrained by the present; the conference imposes real limits [11]. Not everything is possible. But it diverges radically by rejecting the idea of a single, fixed future. The constraints are relational and dynamic, not absolute. This allows for genuine novelty and transformation [12]—something strict determinism can never permit.

It converges with probabilism by wholeheartedly embracing an open future populated by multiple, objective potentials. Probability is real. But it diverges by refusing to see chance as a primitive, unexplainable building block. In the CoD model, probability is an emergent property of the conference of difference. It is the process of transformation itself. that is primitive of existence.

The CoD model’s unique contribution is this shift from a substance-based ontology to a relational ontology. The classical debate focuses on the status of things (events, particles, states). The CoD model focuses on the relations between things as primary. The term, being as 'action to be', is not a static noun but a verb. [13]

The Takeaway: A Universe in Conversation

The centuries-long debate between determinism and probability was never a true opposition. It was a debate about the symptoms, not the cause. The real subject is the modal structure—the architecture of possibility—and the CoD model provides a compelling blueprint.

It resolves the conflict by showing us a universe that is both reliable and open, constrained and creative. The future is not a single line of dominoes waiting to fall, nor is it a cloud of pure randomness. It is a complex, unfolding conference of difference, a continuous process where differences meet, relate, and transform. The deterministic meta-process ensures the conversation never stops. The probabilistic outcomes ensure the conversation is always transforming.

This model leaves us with a profound and exciting challenge: how can we formalize this philosophical framework into a rigorous mathematical structure? How can it directly interact with and inform our best scientific theories, like quantum mechanics? The architecture is now visible. The next step is to build upon it. The conference is ongoing, and you are invited to participate.[14]

The Gospel of Being cover

The Gospel of Being

by John Mackay

A rigorous yet readable exploration of how existence functions—and how that relates to you.

Discover the book


Footnotes

  1. Aristotle. (1994). De interpretatione [On interpretation]. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle: The revised Oxford translation (Vol. 1, pp. 25-38). Princeton University Press. (Original work published ca. 350 B.C.E.) ↩︎

  2. Howard, D. (2024). The Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. In E. N. Zalta & U. Nodelman (Eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2024 ed.). Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2024/entries/qm-copenhagen/ ↩︎

  3. Goldstein, S. (2021). Bohmian mechanics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 ed.). Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/qm-bohm/ ↩︎

  4. This is a reference to Humean Supervenience, a philosophical doctrine most closely associated with David Lewis. It proposes that everything that exists in the world—including laws of nature—supervenes on (i.e., is entirely determined by) the vast mosaic of local physical events, or "Humean facts," spread throughout space and time. In this view, laws of nature are not prescriptive governing entities that force events to happen. Instead, they are merely descriptive, human-constructed summaries of the patterns and regularities that happen to occur within that cosmic mosaic. The laws are simply the most efficient and informative way to compress all of these individual events into a coherent system. Therefore, the "necessity" we associate with laws is not a feature of the world itself, but a product of our systematization of it. ↩︎

  5. Mackay, J.I., (2024) Gospel of Being. ISBN: 978-0-6480983-2-4 ↩︎

  6. Ibid, 1.1 p.16. and 1.7 p.46. ↩︎

  7. Ibid. 3.5, p.104. and 3.7, p.112 ↩︎

  8. Ibid. 2.1, p.51 and 2.5, p.71 ↩︎

  9. Ibid. 7.1, p.194 and 8.1, p.233 ↩︎

  10. Amendment: this sentence previously read: 'It is the living, evolving 'measure of knowing together' that defines, at any given moment, the current landscape of potential relations and necessities'. This original was more explanatory of sentient being as opposed to non-sentient being and was thus amended to be explanatory of both. (2025-09-21) ↩︎

  11. Ibid. 3.2, p.92 and 3.5, p.104 ↩︎

  12. Ibid. 10.5, p.302 and 10.6, p.306 ↩︎

  13. Ibid. 6.1, p.171 and 7.1, p.194 ↩︎

  14. Initial drafts of this article were created with the assistence of DeepSeek R1, with records of conversations retained. Any errors or omissions, in published form however, are mine alone. ↩︎